ON GENDER
DIFFERENCE RESEARCH
|
|
"There
are more methodological problems in regards to the study of
cognitive sex differences, and sex differences in general, than
there are actual sex differences."
|
|
|
|
This
is both a profound and rather remarkable statement to be made by
one of the leading researchers in the field of sex-difference
research. Yet, it is the principal point made by Carolyn Jacklin
during a lecture she presented on sex-related research.
Throughout her presentation Jacklin discusses one methodological
problem after another, including small and inconsistent findings,
publication bias, definitional problems and inappropriate
conclusions drawn from available data; and at the end of her talk
Jacklin concludes that "much past research has not been done
very well." Jacklin does not suggest, however, that
sex-difference research should be discontinued; rather, she urges
her audience to do better research in the future. Given all
the fundamental methodological problems that Jacklin raises, it
might be equally valid to ask why such research should be
continued. Whose interest does it serve? In what way
does this research enhance our understanding of human behavior?
The
goal of scientific research is to develop theories and models that
lead to better and better predictions of behavior, be it the
behavior of physical objects in space, molecules in living
organisms, or individuals in society. Predictability is,
thus, fundamental to doing science. Yet, Jacklin clearly
states that predictability is one of the things that is severely
lacking in sex-difference research. According to Jacklin,
"we gain little in prediction by knowing the sex of a
child." Indeed, the largest sex difference found
concerns "rough and tumble" play among 4-year olds, and
this amounted in one study to only 15%. This means that with
regard to this "trait", 85% of boys are
indistinguishable from 85% of girls. This is not a very big
difference, certainly not the clear typological difference
pictured by many people, including many professional social and
behavioral scientists. Furthermore, this specific
differences did not even concern a cognitive difference; When
discussing cognitive traits, the differences are much less.
Caplan and Caplan in
Thinking
Critically About Research on Sex and Gender
(1998) state
that in those studies that show cognitive differences, those
differences range between 1-5%. At the same time, there are
many studies --perhaps the majority-- that show no differences at
all. This means that between 95 and 100% of men and women
show no differences in cognitive abilities. How valid is it
then to make claims of significant sex difference when such small
differences are routinely found, and when in a large proportion of
the cases no differences are found?
According
to Jacklin, we need even to be skeptical of those studies that
purport to find sex differences. She points out that many of
the differences found are simply a function of small sample
size. One important study suggesting sex differences in
chemical sensitivity, for example, was based on only 3 men and 3
women. Another study claiming sex differences in brain
lateralization was based on the analysis of only 9 male brains and
5 female brains (Caplan & Caplan). How valid is it to
claim the existence of sex differences based on research using
such small samples? How valid are claims made for studies of
even 40 or 50 individuals? The tendency to combine the
research of numerous independent studies into a single statistical
analysis (in order to obtain the large numbers required to
determine statistical significance) simply compounds the problem.
As Caplan & Caplan point out, by combining many individual
studies into a "meta-analysis," small insignificant
differences obtained through separate research (whose
methodologies have no connection to one another) are magically
transformed into a pseudo-significant "single" study,
the conclusions of which are questionable.
The
composition of the samples used in studies of sex differences also
raises problems. Such research is mostly based on American
subjects. According to Jacklin, very little cross-cultural
research exists, and what little research has been done outside
the U.S. has been done in England among comparable social
groups. Indeed, according to a recent article in the
American Anthropologist, 80% of the articles published in social
psychology journals are based on research conducted on students in
Introduction to Psychology classes. How are such studies
(and by extension sex-difference studies) biased by the
composition of their sample populations? Might not the
results be different if the studies were based on students in
Anthropology, Chemistry or Art courses, let alone on working-class
individuals who did not go to college, individuals in minority
communities, or those living on the Navajo Reservation or in
African villages?
Another
critical problem raised by both Jacklin, and Caplan
& Caplan,
is the problem of defining the variables under
investigation. Fundamental to the scientific process is the
use of clearly definable concepts amenable to testing and,
therefore to either verification or falsification. While
such concepts as "verbal ability", 'math ability"
and "spatial visualization" are treated in the
literature as unitary concepts, as with "intelligence"
they are a composite of a variety of specific characteristics and
skills that may or may not vary together. An individual that
is good at one type of computation may not be good at another;
similarly, individuals may vary in which specific verbal skills
they excel and in which they do poorly. To combine these
individual skills together into a single unitary concept called
verbal ability, math ability or spatial visualization amounts to a
reification of those concepts --in the same way that
combining the vast array of individual skills into a unitary
concept called "intelligence" represents a reification
of that concept. It then becomes highly problematic to claim that
different studies using different operational definitions of
verbal ability are all, in fact, measuring verbal ability, and
thus verifying sex differences for verbal ability.
Given
the fundamental methodological problems associated with
sex-difference research together with the small and insignificant
conclusions obtained from this research, it is reasonable to ask
why such research continues and why the concept of sex difference
persists. Both Jacklin and Caplan & Caplan provide the
same explanation: publication bias. According to
Jacklin, there is "a tremendous bias towards the indexing,
publishing, citing and remembering of a positive
instance." She suggests that claims for a difference
are likely to be based on one study in 20 --to her a chance
phenomenon. Caplan & Caplan cite one study that showed a
sex difference in spatial abilities among white children but not
among black children. According to them, the white children's
difference was cited in subsequent publications far more
frequently than the Black children's non-difference. To what
extent does such selective bias towards the publication and
subsequent referencing of research purporting to show a positive
sex difference (to the near exclusion of research showing no
differences) create a false image not only among the public, but
also within the social and behavioral science community of larger
and more significant differences than actually exist? Can
this be likened to the "Abuse Bowl" phenomenon?
While
Jacklin only scratches the surface of the problems associated with
sex-difference research, the methodological problems she addresses
raise important issues regarding that research. Given all of
the methodological problems associated with such studies and the
consistently small (and frequently non-existent) differences
found, it is reasonable to ask why such research persists?
Would we continue to conduct such inconclusive research in
physics, chemistry, biology or medicine? Would we continue
to fund research that after 30 years could not point to conclusive
results? Whose interests are being served by such
research?
To what extent might social and political factors contribute to
this persistence? The philosopher of science, Phillip Frank,
proposed two reasons for the acceptance and persistence of
scientific theories: their technical superiority and/or their
social acceptability. Clearly, if both Jacklin and Caplan
& Caplan are correct, sex-difference research has produced
precious little suggestion of sex-related differences in cognitive
behavior. The concept of sex-difference provides little
explanatory power. How might the social and political
developments that have been taking place in higher education
account for the persistence of this research? Might the
continuation of such research serve the interests of college and
university social and behavioral science departments, as well as
professional psychology journals? Could the continued
interest in the topic of sex-difference reflect the
transformation, for example, of psychology from a discipline that
was 67% male in 1975 to one that is 67% female in 1995? If
so, could this persistence simply be a product of the Science
of Self-Preservation as
suggested by Seligman?
|
*
* * *
*
|